As historian of science Anne Harrington dramatized in the introduction to her 1997 edited volume The Placebo Effect, “Placebos are the ghosts that haunt our house of biomedical objectivity, the creatures that rise up from the dark and expose the paradoxes and fissures in our own self-created definitions of the real and active factors in treatment” (p.1). It’s hard to hear this and not think of Marx’s introduction to The Communist Manifesto: “A spectre is haunting Europe — the spectre of communism. All the powers of Europe have entered into a holy alliance to exorcise this spectre …” Marx went on to declare that communism was a finally acknowledged formidable sociopolitical power and that the world was overdue a manifesto penned in its name. Similarly, within the pharmaceutical industry, the placebo effect is seen as a threat to be controlled—pretty literally, it would seem, the power of (the) people to heal themselves.

This article does not pretend to be a manifesto for the placebo, but it argues that the “problems” that the placebo effect has created for the pharmaceutical industry in fact suggest ways past a dominant cultural system in which our endogenous capacity for health is exploited for capital.

The pragmatic if not panicked title of a 2011 article in the journal Schizophrenia Bulletin sounds the alarm: “What Is Causing the Reduced Drug-Placebo Difference in Recent Schizophrenia Clinical Trials and What Can be Done About It?” (Kemp et al.) The article was the outcome of an international meeting of psychiatrists and researchers trying to understand why in clinical trials for new antipsychotic medications since the mid-1990s the placebo effect has been steadily increasing while the drug effect has been steadily decreasing. They wondered, do these newer studies have design flaws? Have the patient populations changed? Has the disease itself changed? Are the new antipsychotics simply less effective than earlier ones? They even considered the rise of so-called “‘professional’ research participants” who have financial motives to remain enrolled in clinical trials and who might therefore exhibit “an apparent eagerness to please the investigators.” The paper’s authors did not arrive at any firm conclusions. But their flailing about for answers suggests that the placebo effect is like an epistemological whack-a-mole: As soon as one confounding factor is explained or controlled for it’s just a matter of time before another pops up.

The authors specifically lamented the dearth of raw clinical trial data that is readily available for re-analysis. However, pharmaceutical companies do not openly share clinical trial data. On the contrary, they “protect” it, firstly by often not publishing unsuccessful trials. But why? On the one hand, it’s perplexing that raw clinical trial data would be kept a secret. So long as the data has not been fraudulently altered, what’s to hide? On the other hand, the entirety of clinical trial data might make a drug look less efficacious than reported in individually successful trials (a mere two of which is what the FDA requires to approve a new drug). Biased publications have characterized the psychiatric drug literature in particular.

Marx offers one explanation: “Political economy conceals the estrangement inherent in the nature of labor by not considering the direct relationship between the worker (labor) and production” (1964, 109-110). The “direct relationship” in the case of the clinical trial would include the participant’s ability—not to generate objective health for capital, but subjective health for its own sake, i.e. the experience of health over and above what is assumed to be given by the therapeutic agent (e.g. pills) directly. Problematized as the placebo effect, this ‘extra’ form of health cannot exploited like surplus labor, for it does not add value to the pill; rather, it is discarded altogether as that which cannot be commodified. (In fact, the placebo effect comes at literal expense to drug companies insofar as it contributes to the failure of clinical trials, whose costs subtract from the eventual surplus value of the drug.)

As a wily form of health, the placebo effect is nonetheless a kind of “estrangement inherent in the nature of labor.” Rather than estrangement that takes the form of a worker putting their labor into producing an object that ultimately cannot be theirs, in the case of the placebo effect it takes the form of an endogenous capacity to produce health that gets disavowed as not-real. This kind of “spontaneously” produced health is rejected because it cannot be objectified as the true “signal” of the drug—a prerequisite for commodification: “High placebo response rates hamper efforts to detect signals of efficacy for new antidepressant medications, contributing to trial failures and delaying the delivery of new treatments to market” (Rutherford & Roose, 2013).

So the clinical trial participant whose improved health is explained away as “only” because of the placebo effect would still seem to be in the very state of alienation Marx described for the worker: “[L]abor is external to the worker, i.e. it does not belong to his essential being; that in his work, therefore, he does not affirm himself but denies himself …” (1964, 110). Clinical trial participants become estranged to their own labor (i.e. the work of producing health) and thus, as Marx would have it, become alienated from themselves. Hence the patient’s self-reproach: “It’s all in my head.”

Pharmaceutical companies hide the majority of these “failed” clinical trial data from the public. As a consequence, most of the clinical trial participant labor that has gone into producing pills-as-commodities is hidden from the consumer, who nonetheless is later invited into a relationship with the FDA-approved (i.e. legitimated) drug as the imminent objectification of their own health.

This is a particularly egregious form of commodity fetishism. As exemplified in the case of antidepressants, the drug becomes an illusion that masks the reality of the clinical trial, namely that the consumer likely does not need the drug to become healthy.

Commodifying the placebo effect via consumerism

Capitalism is remarkable for its ability to assimilate—i.e. commodify—material that might seem outwardly subversive to it (for example, a bestselling book that critiques consumerism). In the case of pharmaceuticals, this has meant devising clever ways to profit from the placebo effect, despite that researchers lament it as increasingly subversive to the clinical trial. But while endogenous self-healing cannot be commodified at the level of the clinical trial, it can be commodified once the drugs have entered the marketplace. One strategy is to exorcise the placebo effect as the ghost of the real, by invoking neuroscience as a kind of biological reductionism.

Interviewed by the industry journal Pharmaceutical Executive, the lead researcher of a study showing that the brain could release endorphins in response to a placebo painkiller claimed, “Placebo effects are physiology, not just psychology,” adding that, “physicians could maximize the impact of real drugs by using the mechanisms of the placebo effect to encourage their patient’s brains to provide additional relief” (Metzler, 2005). Here the placebo effect, while not legitimized to be as “real” as the drug itself, is nonetheless objectified as a market opportunity to become more real than what is accounted for in the clinical trial. The just-psychology of “it’s all in my head” is then redeemed, but only insofar as it can be pressed into the service of the effects of the real-drugs (“maximizing their input”).

The consumer’s endogenous health is finally abstracted and commodified as a kind of labor that equates to the value of the drug. It has become surplus value, since it is health generated over and above what the drug supposedly delivers alone.

The sense in which the placebo effect is rendered “real” through neuroscience is an example of how science can be deployed as ideology in the service of pharmaceutical capitalism. As economist and historian Robert Heilbroner noted:

Science is not ideological in the sense of an avowal of social values, or an overt partisanship for social interests. Its ideological aspect lies rather in the function played by its deepest conception—an indifferent and inert matter as the ultimate stuff of reality. It this provides a world view compatible with, and needed by, that required for the limitless invasion of the world for the purpose of surplus accumulation (1985, 135).

Neuroscience is used to tame the placebo effect (“the ghosts that haunt our house of biomedical objectivity”) as inert in precisely this sense of encouraging surplus accumulation.

The placebo effect can also be commodified after the clinical trial through advertising. Drug marketers in fact have defended the direct-to-consumer advertising of prescription drugs in terms of the placebo effect, which, they argue, could lead to better drug compliance:

These advertising strategies not only create consumer demand for the advertised products, but may also create the emotionally conditioned responses and expectancies instrumental to enhancing a placebo effect that occurs when the medication is taken. This conditioned response may increase the effectiveness of medications beyond that which is expected from their purely biological mechanisms (Almasi et al., 2006).

Note that in this quote it’s not “emotions” (or imagination or mind) that are themselves efficacious, but that they can only enhance the effectiveness of the drug alone. That is, they add value to the drug.

It is striking that the clinical trial—which is what the FDA demands of pharmaceutical companies to connect their drugs to specific illness and to prove that their drugs work as advertised—does not account for marketing itself. Clinical trial participants are not told brand names. They are not shown advertisements. But once in the marketplace, the consumer becomes a producer; endogenous health is appropriated to boost the signal of the drug. So pharmaceutical capitalism wants it both ways, minimizing the placebo effect in clinical trials whose goal is to show a drug’s signal, and maximizing the placebo effect after the drug has entered the marketplace.

It is perhaps ironic that the clinical trial participant whose endogenous production of health was disavowed would then confront it in an externalized (alienated) form in the marketplace as a drug to be purchased. But pharmaceutical capitalism is a cultural institution that disavows our endogenous health, selling it back to us as an objectified commodity.

The industry journal Pharmaceutical Executive has defined the very purpose of the drug marketer as discovering how to make consumers feel discomfort with their own choices and experiences:

[O]ur job as marketers is to change customers’ perceptions, preferences, and behaviors towards our products or services. Our job is to make people uncomfortable enough to change their current behavior. Their comfort is not in our best interest. Left to their own devices, our target customers would choose to stay in their comfort zones, which means they wouldn’t use or even try the product or service we’re ­offering (Topin, 2013).

That is to say, an individual’s satisfaction is antithetical to contemporary capitalism. They must be kept alienated from it in order to keep returning to the marketplace in a perpetual attempt to regain it.

In a recent study published in the prestigious Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, the objective fetishism of neuroscience has met up with the psychological life of drug advertising:

Our results suggest that a commercial phenomenon, television advertising, may be an important trigger for psychologically mediated physiological effects of a drug. Our findings also inform economic theories of advertising. They suggest that, at least in the context of new consumers of pharmaceutical products, advertisements can have a large impact on the efficacy of a drug (Kamenica et al., 2013).

The curious phrase “psychologically mediated physiological effects” implies that the mind or imagination is a passive conduit of the “real” workings of biology. Moreover, the study’s authors are directly cognizant of how their research (especially couched in this framework of biological reductionism) is already at the service of “economic theories of advertising”—that is, the science of the placebo effect is a deliberate strategy on behalf of the political economy of pharmaceutical capitalism.

Sorcery and relentless expansion

In pharmaceutical capitalism, commodity fetishism intersects with what anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss called the “effectiveness of symbols”—the social network of belief necessary to elicit the experience of healing, whether in psychoanalysis or in shamanistic magic. Lévi-Strauss enumerated the components of symbolic efficacy as: “First, the sorcerer’s belief in the effectiveness of his techniques; second, the patient’s or victim’s belief in the sorcerer’s power; and, finally, the faith and expectations of the group, which constantly acts as a sort of gravitational field within which the relationship between sorcerer and bewitched is located and defined” (1972 [1958]). In the case of the placebo effect, the capacity to produce endogenous health is similarly born out of social relationships. This might mean seeking authority in a doctor; or seeking paternal or maternal understanding from a therapist; or seeking “exotic” alternative understandings of bodies, health, and illness. In these various cases, the would-be patient seeks out an authoritative and empathetic knowledge about themselves that is assumed to be possessed by somebody else (“the patient’s belief in the sorcerer’s power”).

At the same time, the placebo effect works on drug researchers. It is now well-established in scientific placebo literature that doctor or researcher expectations influences the placebo effect just as well as patient or participant expectations (“the sorcerer’s belief in the effectiveness of his techniques”).

In addition to a unique doctor-patient dyad being a locus of the placebo effect, it also makes sense to talk about cultural zeitgeist as originating it (“the faith and expectations of the group”). That is, if the placebo effect is based in part on individual expectations, and if those expectations are given culturally (e.g. when antidepressants graced the covers of mainstream magazines and were hailed as miracle drugs), then our individual biological relationship to medications can be mediated by culture.

And, as noted in the beginning of this article, that relationship can change over time. The placebo effect has increased in recent decades the U.S., suggesting that it is under the influence of cultural changes. Statisticians have even invoked “the publication year effect” to describe growing rates of placebo response in antidepressant clinical trials specifically. That is, the more recent the date of a study’s publication, the more likely it is to exhibit a higher placebo response rate (Mora et al., 2011).

From the perspective of the capitalist, this is a problem of overproduction. That is to say, via an increasing placebo effect clinical trial participants produce too much health—but not the kind that can be measured as a drug’s signal. Not only are those participants then confronted with a fraction of their labor in the marketplace as FDA-approved psychiatric drugs to be purchased, but those drugs have seemingly become less and less effective over time. And yet pharmaceutical profits have risen while the effectiveness of pharmaceuticals has fallen (Chalabi, 2013). We are therefore faced with a strange situation analogous to how Marx described the capitalist paradox of overproduction in which workers are forced to live below their means (i.e. not being compensated with adequate medication) because they have produced too much.

The “overproduction” of the placebo response is part of a new global political economy of the pharmaceutical industry to search out so-called “treatment naive” populations. Clinical trial managers have had an increasingly difficult time finding such populations within the U.S., in part because so many Americans consume prescription pharmaceuticals, which leads to confounding drug interactions in the clinical trial. In practice this has also meant identifying populations who are enticed into the clinical trial (including the placebo arm) as a form of health unto itself.

Arif Khan, a psychiatrist who has led hundreds of clinical trials for pharmaceutical companies, provides an ethical justification for placebo-centric healthcare in underdeveloped countries: “The quality of care that placebo patients get in trials is far superior to the best insurance you get in America … It’s basically luxury care” (Silberman, 2009). However, the endgame of a clinical trial is a new therapeutic designed to treat whatever illness those clinical trial participants suffer from in the first place—regardless of whether they are receiving relatively improved interim healthcare as part of a placebo arm. And the exploitative reality is that many of these outsourced clinical trials develop drugs for common chronic diseases that are sold back in wealthy countries—not in the countries whose populations were used in those clinical trials, despite their interim “luxury” care (Glickman et al., 2009).

Anthropologist Adriana Petryna has called this kind of logic “ethical variability,” or how drug companies rationalize providing ultimately substandard medical care compared to what would be offered in more developed countries. These scenarios of globalized pharmaceutical capitalism echo the opprobrious Tuskegee syphilis study, a long-term “experiment” conducted between 1932 and 1972 by the U.S. Public Health Service to examine the “natural” progression of untreated syphilis in rural African American men—continued for decades even after effective treatments had been developed in the mid-1940s. Tuskegee researchers defended withholding active treatments by claiming that the general level of medical care within the study was much higher than the community standard.

On the one hand the globalization of the pharmaceutical industry follows the logic of expanding capital in which cheap labor is seemingly inevitably sought overseas. This is not quite capitalism expanding to find new markets, however, so much as capitalism expanding a still-colonialist version of labor power and seeking out additional “natural resources” (i.e. treatment-naive bodies) to saturate a single (Western, often American) market.

On the other hand the ethical variability of the globalized clinical trial has found its way back inside of the U.S. In an age of rapid-paced managed care, the clinical trial has become a site of longer, potentially more empathetic care. As one research article on the antidepressants acknowledged: “[B]eing assigned to placebo in an antidepressant trial is far from ‘no treatment,’ since it entails intensive contact with health care staff that greatly exceeds what is delivered in standard community treatment.”

Perhaps placebo-as-treatment has reached one logical extreme in a recent unblinded placebo study, which showed that placebos can be experienced as more efficacious compared to no treatment—even if participants and researchers are both aware that a placebo is being administered. It’s important to note, though, that the researchers told these participants that placebos are known to activate one’s own healing responses (Kaptchuk et al., 2010). The study suggests that the “effectiveness of the symbol” does not require deception in the traditional sense of the blinded randomized control trial, although it would seem that medical authority in the form of knowledge about the placebos is still at play (both as “the patient’s belief in the sorcerer’s power” and “the sorcerer’s belief in the effectiveness of his techniques”).

From signal to perturbation

Pharmaceutical researchers are hurriedly trying to deconstruct the placebo effect as the numerous non-pharmacological ways in which we interact with drugs (“psychological,” “cultural,” and so on). This perhaps represents an inadvertent throwback to some of the basic tenants of psychodynamic psychiatry—historically, the dominant form of American outpatient psychiatry when the first generations of psychopharmaceuticals were introduced. Psychodynamic psychiatrists did not worry about the placebo effect as a “ghost that haunts our house of biomedical objectivity”; rather, they assumed that individuals engage with psychiatric medication first and foremost at the level of meaning.

Today’s psychodynamic psychiatrists still insist that, while antidepressants may have “real biochemical effects,” there’s no guarantee that individuals won’t resist, amplify, or invent these effects to express or address psychological needs. Glen Gabbard, Director of the Baylor Psychiatric Clinic, claims that even the very notion of a “chemical imbalance” can become part of a patient’s defensive armature against the psychological work required of talk therapy, precisely by strengthening stubborn pathogenic fantasies about oneself.

Belief in invisible neurologic damage may become part of the effectiveness of the symbol that facilitates healing. But whereas pharmaceutical companies hope that the reductionist biological explanations within antidepressant advertising will bolster the placebo effect (by impressing upon consumers that their suffering is “real”), psychodynamic psychiatrists might skeptically pronounce such an experience of a drug as a “flight into health” (conversely to how Freud described neurotic symptoms as flights into illness—i.e. somaticized escapes from unconscious fears or desires).

Psychiatrist David Mann similarly discusses antidepressants not as simple medical interventions for a clearly-defined, objective underlying pathology, but rather as “perturbations” in a patient’s subjective experience of themselves:

Medication is for people who believe there’s something organically wrong with them, and they want to experience the perturbation … [It’s] also for individuals who are stuck, who wouldn’t otherwise return to therapy. It’s a means of engaging them. They won’t explore their symptoms on the level of meaning yet. They just want to be relieved of these feelings. They want something from me, and we may engage on the level of the symptoms (personal interview).

Within psychodynamic psychiatry there is no ‘true drug response,’ which of course is what the clinical trial demands, and which is what the drug marketer promises. In a sense we are all fundamentally placebo responders within this framework, because consuming an antidepressant starts with a kind of meaning-making that is embodied as much as “just psychological.”

Individual symbolic engagement with psychopharmaceuticals also thwarts the notion of the placebo effect as a generalized, measurable category of experience. Gabbard explains the psychodynamic framework as antithetical to the contemporary clinical trial model:

And going back to your original question – ‘What does psychoanalysis have to contribute [to the development of antidepressants]?’ – it’s that each person is unique, so that you’re always tailoring treatments to an understanding of the individual. And that goes completely against the psychopharmacological way of looking at – everybody we hang into groups, and we’ll give them the same treatment because they all have the same diagnosis (personal interview).

Of course, there is no such thing as a clinical trial with an n of 1. The FDA requires that pharmaceutical companies demonstrate that a given compound is effective not on a particular person but on a particular illness (as defined by an orthodox allopathic medical institution, like the AMA or APA). And as there are no biomarkers for mood disorders, determining whether the compound work entails comparing participants’ subjective reports before and after treatment. Whereas the psychodynamic psychiatrist would be interested in why a unique person had a unique set of experiences on an antidepressant, the pharmaceutical company only cares that the aggregate of individuals’ experiences can be boiled down to a signal for the drug itself.

While we should beware romanticizing the psychodynamic framework of antidepressants, its basic tenets do provide an alternative understanding of how endogenous health involves personal and cultural meaning-making. Moreover, historically psychoanalytic theory has included a socially progressive strand of thought by acknowledging fundamental antagonism between individuals and the culture they find themselves within.

The philosopher Herbert Marcuse praised psychoanalysis both as a therapeutic praxis and as a metapsychological critique of society in this sense. He claimed that psychoanalysis recognizes that ontogenetically sick individuals are really caused by phylogenetically sick societies, and that, beyond personal “health,” the goal of analysis is both to get individuals to see how society is sick, and to get them to function with society “without surrendering to it altogether.”

Symptoms are not mere suffering to be medicated away; they might be signs that some desire (often sexual in nature) has been denied, diverted as a form of anguish for the sake of preserving cultural norms. Symptoms are therefore jumping off points to discuss why an individual suffers, both in terms of their personal history and in terms of how society might be set up so has to deny them self-expression.

Psychedelic perturbations

The apparent next revolution in psychiatric medication is also a return to an old revolution—the therapeutic use of psychedelic plants and fungi (and compounds synthesized from them, like LSD). Before psychedelics were criminalized for sociopolitical reasons in the late 1960s, they were a part of a dramatic new experimental psychopharmacology. Initially CIA experimentalists turned to LSD as a new form of psychological warfare that could be used during interrogations or to disorient enemy soldiers en masse. But they were repeatedly thwarted by the directionality of LSD experiences. It seemed to work like a truth serum on some subjects; it seemed to work like a “lie serum” on others, making them paranoid and uncooperative (Lee & Shlain, 1985, 16). Some subjects experienced overwhelming anxiety; others felt themselves to become omnipotent. At the end of the day, the effects of LSD were simply too wily for the CIA to find strategic usefulness in it.

But such experiential wiliness fit the work of a number of psychiatrists who found LSD elucidative to the work of psychodynamic therapy. Indeed, it was within the psychodynamic context that psychedelics were seen as the ultimate perturbations. Whereas the subsequent generations of psychopharmaceuticals would be intended to control symptoms, psychedelics were intended to generate unique experiences and induce profound personal insight directly. Also unlike psychopharmaceuticals, psychedelics did not have to be taken continuously and indefinitely; a finite number of psychedelic sessions could bring dramatic resolution to a number of malaises including depression and anxiety (Grob et al., 2011) and alcoholism (Hoffer, 1966).

In addition to narrow clinical goals, early psychedelic researchers like Humphry Osmond and Stanislav Grof ruminated on the potential of these substances to change how we understand the very nature of mind (Dyck, 2008). Their writings were as much philosophical treatises on the human mind as clinical accounting of how psychedelics can affect behavioral problems, addiction, or doctor-patient rapport in psychotherapy sessions. Grof, for instance, described psychedelics as revolutionary prods to any serious science of the human: “Many observations from psychedelic research are of such fundamental importance and are so revolutionary in nature that they should not be ignored by any serious scientific interested in the human mind. They indicate an urgent need for drastic revision of some of our theoretical concepts and even the basic scientific paradigms” (1980,10).

We should count among these scientific paradigms the placebo-controlled clinical trial. Indeed, psychedelics fundamentally challenge the role of the placebo effect in psychiatric medicine. After all, what does it mean to pit a placebo against substances that produce intense perceptual distortions including hallucinations and synesthesia, or sudden and rapturous personal insight? The small handful of recent psychedelic studies conducted under the aegis of evidence-based medicine have used “active placebos” including a much smaller dose of the psychedelic compound which might be vaguely detected by the participant but whose effects are not as profound as those brought on by the higher doses given to the experimental groups.

There is an important sense in which psychedelics transcend medical and scientific truth claims. Is a patient’s Prozac working (is there a signal)? Perhaps. But there’s no conclusive way to tell. (After all, maybe it’s “just in their heads.”) But is a patient’s psilocybin or LSD working? Without question. Compared to psychopharmaceuticals, experiences of psychedelics are indubitable.

The fact that we even debate the efficacy of antidepressants points to the heart of the problem. There is no debating that psychedelic experiences can profoundly affect individuals (of course, the content of those altered states of consciousness is shaped by culture and personal histories). But it’s precisely in the epistemological gray area of uncertainty over how well psychopharmaceuticals work where politics and capital insert themselves. Hence the burgeoning marketing literature devoted to exploiting the placebo effect for pharmaceutical profit.

Psychedelics, however, would seem to have the potential to divorce our health from pharmaceutical capitalism. As if their wily nature wasn’t already impractical enough to be commodified as “signal,” the most potent psychedelics are either naturally-occurring plants that cannot be patented, or, in the case of LSD, a semi-synthetic substance whose patent expired in 1963.

Psychedelic truth to pharmaceutical power?

Since the time of Marx’s writing, we have seen increased direct involvement of the state to protect capitalists. This helps us understand the continued repression of psychedelic drugs in Western societies. Pharmaceutical companies are threatened by psychedelics, which cannot be obviously commodified. The state protects their profits from psychopharmaceuticals by refusing to decriminalize psychedelics. That is, the state protects capital at the expense of the people’s health (endogenous health as the people’s inherent capacity to work for themselves).

There is deeper sociopolitical ideology at play here, too, insofar as the history of psychedelics in the U.S. is the history of their being associated with anti-war, “counter-culture” youths whose experiences of psilocybin and LSD were often phrased in terms of “opening the mind” and seeing through the bullshit of political power structures. As Marcuse wrote in 1969: “Today’s rebels want to see, hear, feel new things in a new way: they link liberation with the dissolution of ordinary and orderly perception. The ‘trip’ involves the dissolution of the ego shaped by the established society …” (1969). To the New Left movements of the 1960s, cognitive and perceptual revolution was a prerequisite for true, lasting political revolution.

The ethnobotanist and psychonaut Terence McKenna would revisit this notion in the 1990s:

It doesn’t matter whether you’re a Hasid, a communist apparatchik, a rainforest shaman, if you take psychedelics you will question your first premises; and that is a business that all governments—right, left, middle—are in the business of repressing. They don’t want to have to explain why things are done as they are. But if we don’t begin asking for that explanation, they’re going to run this planet right into ruin.

It is a tantalizing idea that a drug itself could induce politically subversive thought. We certainly don’t talk that way about psychopharmaceuticals. On the contrary, the history of antidepressant and anxiolytic advertising gets repeatedly critiqued for how it has reinforced sexist or otherwise repressively normative social roles (see Greenslit, 2006, and Metzl, 2003).

Some have even argued that the very word “drug” is a misnomer when it comes to psychedelic plants and fungi. McKenna, for instance, was insistent that substances like psilocybin-containing mushrooms and DMT-containing ayahuasca were not drugs, but “events.” They did not treat symptoms; they imparted experiences that could change one’s understanding of their role in the world. Moreover the language of “drugs” invokes the work of manufacturing, licensing, and medical gatekeeping—all state-protected enterprises that arguably do not—and should not—apply to plants or fungi.

As the comedian Bill Hicks once quipped, “Doesn’t the idea of making nature illegal seem a little … unnatural to you?” This plaint echoes Marx’s observation about the separation of labor from land. On the one hand this meant subordinating the land to capitalist exploitation. On the other hand, in the case of natural psychedelics like shrooms or yagé, this has meant preventing access to nature altogether. But as pharmaceutical capitalists need to own the means of production of health, so too do they need to prevent the people from acquiring their own means to produce the same.

In light of the grip of pharmaceutical capitalism, one strategy to reintroduce psychedelics into mainstream American culture has been to medicalize them. Organizations like MAPS (the Multidisciplinary Association for Psychedelic Studies) have been receiving DEA approval for small clinical trials that are demonstrating what researchers in the 1950s and 1960s already knew: Psychedelic substances can alleviate anxiety and depression, and can increase people’s general sense of spiritual well-being (for lack of better description).

MAPS’s contemporary strategy, though, is to push psychedelics through the culturally sanctioned institution of evidence-based clinical medicine, eventually to get them approved by the FDA as prescription drugs. As its founder and spokesperson Rick Doblin said optimistically of the process: “The FDA really does respond to attempts to alleviate suffering and to promote healing in patients. Their primary mission is not to support the war on drugs, their primary is to work to develop medicines to treat patients” (Doblin, 2001).

The question is whether this will end up trading sociopolitical control in form of criminalization for control in the form of medical gatekeeping and perpetuated pharmaceutical capitalism. Psychedelics seem inherently less amenable to the sorceries of belief that characterize the political economy of today’s psychopharmaceuticals, including the strange relationship between the placebo effect and the extraction of value from the drug.

Following Lévi-Strauss, the placebo effect—the “effective symbol”—hinges on belief. But culturally perhaps we need to push past belief-in-pharmaceuticals to the more indomitable experiential knowledge that psychedelics would seem to enable, namely trading symptom relief for therapeutic insight into oneself and one’s society. Because belief in this case teeters dangerously close to the capitalist ideology of “drugs for life” (Dumit, 2012) that sustains the cultural hegemony of the pharmaceutical industry.

This is not a naïve clarion call to an idyllic or nostalgic psychedelic free-for-all. Rather it’s a call to challenge the ideology of pharmaceutical capitalism, to replace our dependency on technocratic expertise and medical gatekeeping with revitalized community-based traditions in which knowledge of psychedelics is shared and openly transmitted to future generations. As the pharmaceutical industry has grown exponentially exploitative during the 35 years since Stanislav Grof wrote about the need to revamp the basic premises of psychology, it’s high time we finally acted on that sense of urgency. Pharmaceutical-centric psychology has failed to offer us a way to save ourselves. And most psychedelic substances are illegal in the U.S. But if we can rebalance our relationships to drugs, perhaps we can change the world. We face the hopeful chance that a return to plant-based psychedelic medicine will unravel major socioeconomic problems associated with the “war on drugs,” from the global militaristic offenses against “terror,” to rising incarceration rates, to exacerbated race and class disparities.

At the very least a new turn to psychedelic healing might offer us a way out of the forms of state-supported capitalism that are depriving us of basic human rights to generate our own health and explore our own minds—without paying for the privilege to do so.

REFERENCES

Almasi, Elizabeth, Randall Stafford, Richard Kravitz, and Peter Mansfield. 2006. What are the public health effects of direct-to-consumer drug advertising? PLoS Medicine. 3.3.

Chalabi, Mona. 2013. Antidepressants: global trends. The Guardian. Available at http://www.theguardian.com/news/2013/nov/20/mental-health-antidepressants-global-trends

Doblin, Rick. 2001. Ecstasy: The medicine, science, and culture of MDMA. Available at http://www.maps.org/mdma/rd020204.html

Dumit, Joseph. 2012. Drugs for Life: How Pharmaceutical Companies Define Our Health. Duke University Press.

Dyck, Erika. Psychedelic Psychiatry: From Clinic to Campus. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Glickman, Seth, John McHutchison, Eric Peterson, Charles Cairns, Robert Harrington, Robert Califf, and Kevin Schulman. 2009. Ethical and scientific implications of the globalization of clinical research. The New England Journal of Medicine. 360:816-823.

Greenslit, Nathan. 2005. Depression and consumption: psychopharmaceuticals, branding, and new identity practices. Culture, Medicine, and Psychiatry. 29(4):477-502.

Grob, Charles, Alicia Danforth, Gurpreet Chopra, Marycie Hagerty, Charles McKay, Adam Halberstadt, and George Greer. 2011. Pilot study of psilocybin treatment for anxiety in patients with advanced-stage cancer. Archives of General Psychiatry. 68(1): 71-8.

Grof, Stanislav. 1980. LSD Psychotherapy. Hunter House.

Harrington, Anne (Ed.) 1997. The Placebo Effect: An Interdisciplinary Exploration. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Kamenica, Erica, Robert Naclerio, and Anup Malani. 2013. Advertisements impact the physiological efficacy of a branded drug. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 110(32): 12931–1293.

Kaptchuk. Ted, Friedlander E, Kelley JM, Sanchez MN, Kokkotou E, et al. 2010. Placebos without deception: a randomized controlled trial in irritable bowel syndrome. PLoS ONE. 5(12):e15591.

Kemp, Aaron, Nina Schooler, Amir Kalali, Larry Alphs, Ravi Anand, George Awad, Michael Davidson, Sanjay Dubé, Larry Ereshefsky, Georges Gharabawi, Andrew C. Leon, Jean-Pierre Lepine, Steven G. Potkin, and An Vermeulen. 2010. What is causing the reduced drug-placebo difference in recent schizophrenia clinical trials and what can be done about it? Schizophrenia Bulletin. 36(3): 504–509.

Heilbroner, Robert. 1985. The Nature and Logic of Capitalism. New York: W.W. Norton.

Hoffer, Abram. 1966. Treatment of alcoholism using LSD as the main variable. Prisma.

Lee, Martin, and Bruce Shlain. 1985. Acid Dreams: The Complete Social History of LSD: The CIA, the Sixties, and Beyond. New York: Grove Press.

Lévi-Strauss, Claude 1972 (1958). Structural Anthropology, Vol. 1. Penguin Books.

Marcuse, Herbert. 1969. An Essay on Liberation. Available at http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/marcuse/works/1969/essay-liberation.pdf

Marx, Karl. 1964. Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844. New York: International Publishers.

Marx, Karl, and Frederick Engels. 1969 (1848). Manifesto of the Communist Party. In Marx/Engels Selected Works, Vol. One. Moscow: Progress Publishers.

Metzl, Jonathan. 2003. Prozac on the Couch: Prescribing Gender in the Era of Wonder Drugs. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

Metzler, Natasha. 2005. Placebo effect: all in the brain. Pharmaceutical Executive. August 25.

Mora, Meike Shedden, Yvonne Nestoriuc, and Winfried Rief. 2011. Lessons learned from placebo groups in antidepressant trials. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society. 366: 1879–1888.

Rutherford, Bret, and Steven Roose. 2013. A model of placebo response in antidepressant clinical trials. American Journal of Psychiatry. 170:723-733.

Silberman, Steve. 2009. The placebo problem Big Pharma’s desperate to solve. Wired. September 14.

Topin, Al. 2013. The art and science of creating discomfort. Pharmaceutical Executive. September 1.

It’s called “How Neuroscience Reinforces Racist Drug Policy”: http://www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2014/06/how-bad-neuroscience-reinforces-racist-drug-policy/371378/

My band Bury Me Standing has been recording new songs with our new singer / violinist Yasmine Azaiez. Here’s a sampling:

thoughtful or neglectful?

February 27, 2012

This blog is perhaps woefully out of date. But, who knows, it’s an experiment to begin with. So maybe its posts are remarkably timed with what you should be paying attention to, precisely when you’re meant to pay attention to it.

During the past couple of months I have been performing and recording with Emperor Norton’s Stationary Marching Band and What Time It It, Mr. Fox? (wait, why do I keep finding myself in musical projects whose names are as ponderous as books that start with phrases like, “Call me Ishmael”?) And I’m about to go into the studio with my (and my partner Vessela Stoyanova’s) twisted psychedelic-metal-meets-Balkan-folk-song creation, Bury Me Standing. That session promises bloodshed of one form or another, so … suffice it to say I’m getting grounded. We’re recording on the leap year, no less.

The writing is plodding along. I have a small piece coming out in Wired tomorrow. And a nerdy-but-accessible piece about sociopolitical and experiential crises associated with psychopharmaceuticals, coming out in the Yale Journal of Biology and Medicine next month.

More. Soon.

Sooner.

This Is Bananas

September 19, 2011

(This was part of my first pitch to Cracked. It turns out they did a piece about the history of the global banana trade a couple years back. So you, fine reader, are the beneficiaries of these comedic dregs. Enjoy. BTW, my first actually-published Cracked article can be found here.)

***********************************

You probably knew that your Nike’s are made by forced child labor in Pakistan and Cambodia. But that’s cool, because everybody knows that. And old news = taken-for-granted = guilt-free jogging or snacking in place! But maybe you didn’t know that the most mundane foods that you eat every day have been brought to you by brutal political oppression and murder? Well, read on, and feel like an asshole all over again!

BANANAS

Americans eat more bananas per year than apples and oranges combined. That’s really fucked up, considering that both apples and oranges are native to the U.S., whereas bananas originally came from the other hemisphere.

Bananas were introduced to the U.S. in 1876 at the nation’s Centennial Exhibition in Philadelphia. It was thus perhaps no coincidence that these exotic little yellow phalluses would predate the erection of Washington Monument by just a few years.

Talk about an exhibitionist!

On the other hand, initial sales of bananas were weak. This was the prudish Victorian era, after all, where the socially elite one-upped future 12-year-olds everywhere, by thinking that eating a banana looked like sucking a dick.

In the future, bananas would be outright named after dicks

The United Fruit Company (which would later be renamed to the I think less catchy sounding “Chiquita”) launched its own anti-prude advertising campaign, distributing postcards that depicted hoity-toity, morally upstanding women sitting around a table with half-peeled bananas. Showing off such culinary circle jerks worked, apparently, and bananas became all the rage.

No, seriously, banana importation caused so, so much rage. Like when Samuel Zamurray (who would later head up United Fruit) just straight up took land from people in Central America, essentially turning the Honduras into his personal private plantation. The balls on this guy. He loaded up boats with a small army led by mercenaries with Saturday morning cartoon-sounding names like General Lee Christmas and Guy “Machine Gun” Maloney, and proceeded to install a government who looked more favorably upon being a fake government. You know what was even more of a dick move? He forced the very people whose land he took to work on it as de facto slave labor.

 

“What a delightful coincidence these bananas fit up your asses so perfectly!”

With such low labor costs (zero is low, right?), United Fruit transported and sold these bananas to Americans so that, despite traveling 1,000 miles, they were actually cheaper than the apples that you could buy next fucking door.

“Hey, you can’t spell emissions without MISSION!”

No, wait, this get so much better. To keep banana prices low, the U.S. government got in on the act, and has even overthrown a government or two in Central America. Like, in the 1950s, The United Fruit Company started a propaganda campaign that Ecuador was a rising communist power in cahoots with the Soviet Union, and was taking the land that United Fruit stole paid fair price for, and giving it to the fucking people they stole it from in the first place insurgent commies. But here’s the thing. They got the fucking C.I.A. in on this shit. The U.S. quickly deposed the democratically elected government, and replaced it with a military junta.

But whatevs. As so much political oppression is solved with cartoons, and as Chiquita just so happened to need an advertising mascot, they went with the obvious choice of turning Carmen Miranda into a singing jaundiced penis, who came into every American home, urging us not to refrigerate our bananas. You see, the peels of refrigerated bananas turn black, which, as every 1950s household feared, once you go black, you never go back.

But, what’s this? After decades of painstaking yet foolishly daredevil research, it has been discovered that refrigerated bananas last longer, and taste juuuuust fine. But you probably won’t use up your bananas as quickly, which means you and your bloated wallet are kind of being a shitbag towards Chiquita.

Thank god the 1950s are over, and all of this is behind us.

Whoops. Nope. Wrong. The U.S. Marines have since been used to put down banana worker strikes and other efforts to organize themselves. And Chiquita has very recently paid millions of dollars to Colombian paramilitary groups to protect its banana harvesting zones. Dudes, as of 2007, Chiquita has been dealing with what could end up being the biggest terrorism-related lawsuit in history, in which the associated death toll is three times that of the World Trade Center attacks.

The rest of us live in the fucking Matrix:

What other name would an American clothing store choose for itself, but a derogatory epithet that references the global political oppression of O.G. jungle capitalism!


Speaking of the Matrix, this story wouldn’t be complete without some techno-horror genetics-gone-wrong component. Indeed. 99% of the bananas we eat now are of the “Cavendish” variety (surely named as such because its letters can be rearranged to get “I vend cash”). These are now all genetically engineered to be the inbred retarded dalmatians of the fruit world.

Not dalmatians, but bananas. Not Cruella DeVille, but Chiquita Brands International

Cavendish bananas are all technically sexless and sterile (so I especially appreciate the irony that so, so many people have gotten fucked over by them). They are also highly susceptible to fungus diseases, especially the insult-to-injury named “Panama Disease.”

A close-up of the Panama fungi

Just like bloated cookie-cutter hair metal bands from the 1980s, this is what happens when massively cloned fruit goes globe-trotting. They get the fucking clap. Cavendish bananas from Ecuador might be resistant to a particular fungus, but then they’re brought to Asia, where they run up against mutated version of it. Hence the Panama Disease, which can wipe out entire plantations in a matter of a couple of years, has been spreading across that other hemisphere, and experts predict that it will come full circle to Central America soon. So the people there, whose lands were stolen from them, and who were essentially enslaved to work on said lands, and whose political economies depend entirely on MOTHERFUCKING BANANAS, could very well lose their one tyrannically imposed livelihood.

But they are still delicious on corn flakes, so I’m really torn.

(A comment on my last blog entry got me thinking more about the relationship between drugs, politics and free will. This post is my first sustained response to that comment.)

Historically, we have been deeply ambivalent towards psychotropic drugs, wondering what (if any) role they should have in society. I would even argue that drugs are at the heart of all political philosophy. Indeed, you already know the politics behind the following questions: Are drugs ‘themselves’ dangerous (are they like guns)? Is drug use truly the activity of a free, rational, autonomous individual? Or, does one not truly act ‘voluntarily’ if they are under the influence of drugs, essentially making them less able to make ‘free choices’? What, then, should be the status of drug users’ civil liberties?

John Stuart Mill, whose nineteenth-century political philosophy was the direct precursor to modern-day libertarianism, emphasized that, “Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign.” Mill address the question of drugs specifically, arguing that any self-harm that comes from drug use should be punishable only insofar as it directly affects others (his example is being drunk while performing soldierly duties). That is to say, members of society should be held criminally responsible only for those behaviors that harm others. Do not criminalize the use of drugs; criminalize the resultant actions that may harm others.

Of course, the case for a paternalistic drug policy can be made on the argument that the notion of true self liberty is a complete fiction. Harming oneself inevitably affects others, whether in the form of a drain on public medical services (health problems), or a drain on social services (family neglect), or on social security (unemployment). Mill’s solution was simply to disregard these cases, defining harm to others as narrowly as possible, for instance as defraudment or physical violence. “Indirect” effects like the eventual use of social services did not count in his framework.

I am definitely attracted to the social ideal behind Mill’s proto-libertarian political philosophy, which was that we should live in a society that enables “experiments of living.” In On Liberty, he writes:

The majority, being satisfied with the ways of mankind as they now are (for it is they who make them what they are), cannot comprehend why those ways should not be good enough for everybody; and what is more, spontaneity forms no part of the ideal of the majority of moral and social reformers, but is rather looked on with jealousy, as a troublesome and perhaps rebellious obstruction to the general acceptance of what these reformers, in their own judgment, think would be best for mankind. (1859, Ch.3)

Mill emphasizes the development of one’s own individuality as a hallmark of a free, democratic society. Essentially saying: “get yo’ freak on!” He warns against the kind of paternalistic government that would essentially predetermine what kinds of lives, personalities and characters are socially valuable, and therefore individually permissible. So drugs may ruin our lives, but it’s of paramount importance that we live in a society that allows us to include them in our individual “experiments of living” — which, of course, could very well turn out disastrously.

But still, one argument against drug-taking is that it is essentially an irrational act, antithetical to the civil ideal of a society made up of rational, autonomous citizens. (Therefore, if drug-taking is not truly a free act, the government should be paternalistic and prevent us from possessing them). This argument can be applied to the decision to take drugs in the first place, or to whether the citizen-on-drugs is a ‘fully rational’ participant in a civil society. That is, either drugs are inherently without value, and pursuing them in the first place is irrational; or, consuming drugs incapacitates or debilitates individuals to the point of making them less rational, less autonomous, and essentially less capable of participating in a ‘free society.’ But I think both boil down to a fundamental confusion between personal freedom and political liberty. And I would argue that, c’est la vie, the integrity of civil liberties risks the compromise of personal freedom. It’s easy to see how an individual’s drug use might made them ‘less free,’ in the sense that they may become unhealthy, irresponsible, destitute, miserable. Their personal, everyday experience of freedom would then become compromised. Yet their civil liberties would have remained intact, since (hypothetically) they ‘freely’ made a decision — albeit a poor one — for themselves. And isn’t this the more important social ideal? [I put ‘freely’ in scare quotes because, of course, there’s no absolute freedom, as if we lived in social vacuums and as if our individual decisions weren’t overdetermined socially and culturally. But I’ll bracket this discussion (addressing behavorial economics, too) for a later post …]

As to the question of whether drugs have ‘inherent’ value, I hasten to mention that public debates about drug policy almost always avoid discussing positive effects of illicit drugs. As Bakalar & Grinspoon put it in their book Drug Control in a Free Society, “Permitting drug use is often defended in the name of individual freedom but rarely on the ground that there is any good in it.” (1984:16) This is another challenge to personal freedom and political liberty, but from a different angle: Nevermind whether drug use makes an individual less free; if drugs are inherently without value, then trying to obtain them in the first place is irrational, and should be prevented by the government. But we already know how contentious and ultimately wrong-headed this claim is. The fact that we now have the phrase “medical marijuana” speaks to the political compromises that simultaneously belie and reveal how this drug has positive effects. But the politics here is that marijuana’s positive effects have to be framed as social (“medical”), not personal.

Of course, there would seem to be numerous other demonstrable social boons from drug use. The historical connections between drugs and art and music certainly jump to mind, which are perhaps most visible in part because of the counter-culture posturing that has been a core component of artists’ and musicians’ collective identity (drugs as badges of anti-authoritarianism). At the same time, where artists and musicians have not flaunted their drug use, mainstream media has all too often stepped in to create their own mythologies-cum-scandals about such behavior. Check out this nice clip of a young Paul McCartney calling out the media for creating and bloating the very scandals about his acid use that they claim to have merely identified and reported on:


Download YouTube Video | YouTube to MP3 | Replay Media Catcher

 

Keith Richards also comes to mind, as the iconic drugged-out, infinitely parodied how-the-fuck-is-he-still-alive rock star. But read his autobiography. Jesus, this guy is articulate [yes, I realize the book is co-authored with a bonafide journalist], funny, and can recall his life with an extraordinary level of detail that puts my 35-year-old brain to shame (as he snipes in the book’s inscription: “Believe it or not, I remember everything”). Moreover, while Richards fully admits to near-constant drug use for his whole career, if we are to believe his narrative, he has never been in serious medical trouble because of it (his legal and political problems have been another story).

Many of us are familiar with how figures like Mark Twain, Sigmund Freud, Baudelaire, Jean Cocteau all used drugs to some extent. But also, some of our most prominent contemporary scientists and engineers credit their revolutionary developments in part to their experimentation with drugs. Kary Mullis, Nobel Laureate who invented the polymerase chain reaction (PCR) as a technique to make copies of DNA fragments, says he learned to visualize DNA because of his experiences on LSD. Similarly, Microsoft co-founder Bob Wallace claims that the birth of early Silicon Valley technologies was influenced by psychedelic drugs, crediting his own invention of shareware–which transformed software distribution–with his experiences with psychedelics. In a documentary on the use of LSD in scientific experiments Wallace says, “I think psychedelics help you in general go beyond the normal way of doing things, and to really open up your mind to more possibilities that maybe seem obvious in retrospect but that you never think of if you’re going along the normal way of doing things.”


Download YouTube Video | YouTube to MP3 | Replay Media Catcher

 

I do not intend these examples as a naively one-sided celebration of drugs that most certainly have the potential to damage or kill us. I intend them as counter-examples to policy-level debates about decriminalization that ignore the very questions of whether and how drugs can have positive effects.

In the middle there is always this:

 

Drugs are bad. But psychopharmaceuticals, on the other hand …

(from The New Yorker)

Some of my ethnographic research around psychopharmaceutical advertising has been to explore what drug companies say beyond the FDA-mandated package insert information. As I discussed in my last blog entry, the discourse of psychopharmaceutical advertising is that antidepressants and antipsychotics realize a return to self (never a way to “explore” or “transcend” the self, which is outside of our normative sociomedical discourse). In terms of civil liberties, it would seem that, so long as you are taking licit psychopharmaceuticals, your free, rational autonomy is guaranteed. So much so, in fact, that the drug companies combine the pharmacological return to self with the consumerist discourse of self-empowerment (You know what’s wrong with you / You should talk to your doctor / You should ‘take control’ of your symptoms). All this is fine and good — and distinctly libertarian-sounding, incidentally — but of course the end-game here is profit maximization for the drug industry, whose “Be Yourself, Take Antidepressants” insinuation is isomorphic to every other advertising slogan that gets hurled at us.

On the other hand, occasionally the drug companies slip up in what their ads reveal about an ideal, fantasized relationship to psychopharmaceuticals. Just days after 9-11, Pfizer released a public relations spot, basically patting themselves on the back for donating to the American Red Cross. But check out this line from the ad’s voiceover: “We wish we could make a medicine that could take away the heartache. Until we can …” This ad aired only very briefly, but luckily my dissertation advisor Joe Dumit was able to record it. I have since posted it on YouTube, with the following description: “In their rush to broadcast a touching bit of PR immediately after the World Trade Center attacks, Pfizer said what it wanted to say (we make medicines, we perform acts of social good). But they ended up promising much, much more (we will make drugs that cure heartache). The pharmaceutical vision of goodwill here is that of a company who eradicates the collective emotional response to a national tragedy.”


Download YouTube Video | YouTube to MP3 | Replay Media Catcher

In terms of political philosophy and the question of free will, the Pfizer ad lets slip the idea that it’s perfectly permissible for a giant corporation to be in the business of selling drugs that chemically manage citizens’ emotional processing of geopolitical trauma. For the record, I do not actually think this should be illegal. HOWEVER, I think it is highly hypocritical of our society to allow such widescale psychotropic drug-mongering on the one hand, while criminalizing our personal decisions to make our own chemical “experiments in living.”

I’ll end this post with a spot-on Chris Rock clip. He says, “The government doesn’t want you to use your drugs, they want you use their drugs. So every night on TV, you see a weird-ass drug commercial trying to get you hooked on some legal shit. And they just keep naming symptoms until they get one that you fucking got.”


Download YouTube Video | YouTube to MP3 | Replay Media Catcher

“Be a philosopher, be a mummy … and away, above all with the body, that pitiable idée fixe of the senses! Infected with every error of logic there is, refuted, impossible even, notwithstanding it is impudent enough to behave as if it actually existed!”

Here Friedrich Nietszche mocks the longstanding Western philosophical tradition that exalts something called ‘Reason’ over the perpetually unreliable, fallible and deceitful ‘senses.’ Nietszche indicts Plato, Christian theology, and uber-positivist scientists alike of buying into and disseminating a giant moralistic LIE that there is a ‘true world’ that we can access, if only we can unshackle ourselves from our inferior / sinful / inaccurate bodies.

Modern-day Dream Theater is just as shitty of an experience ...

Flagellants sure knew how to party

Müller-Lyer's optical illusion: eyes? more like lies!

Pharmaceutical marketing is one of today’s ultimate snake-oil philosopher kings. Remember the television and magazine ads for Pfizer’s “antidepressant” Zoloft?

The putative “chemical imbalance” of these ubiquitous ads updates Nietzsche’s complaint about moralistic, arrogant-yet-idle philosophizing as a modern-day capitalist ideology: The ad’s refrain condescends, “When you know more about what’s wrong, you can help make it right.” This is paternalistic philosophizing, too, albeit one that hands over a deeply personal, social and culturally complicated construct like “depression” to a literally cartoonish scientific expertise, whose ultimate end-game is profit maximization.

Profit, indeed. We’re talking BILLIONS of dollars (according to industry tracker IMS Health, antidepressant sales alone brought in $9b in 2009). In just over a decade, what was once a relatively unknown illness has turned into a mammoth global industry that, in a nutso Orwellian turn, has had so many people taking antidepressants that these drugs have literally ended up in our water supply.

pharm fresh!

Say wha?

Crazy. And a big reason for why antidepressants have become so commonplace is because of the massive marketing campaigns that the pharmaceutical industry has launched over the past decade, which have relied heavily on the rhetorical sway of neuroscientific language and imagery in these ads.

With this in mind, here’s my critique of the psychopharmaceutical industry, in a nutshell (yes, it dawns on me that I should start using “nutshell” to refer to antidepressant pills themselves):

(1) Whether antidepressants ‘work’ at all is completely up for grabs

Through the Freedom of Information Act, analyses of ALL the antidepressant clinical trial data that drug companies have conducted (and not just the ones submitted to the FDA) suggest that antidepressants do not work significantly better than placebos. (For a nice review of this predicament, see Steve Silberman’s 2009 Wired article.) Of course, this is a real slap to the face of the notion that antidepressants work because they target biochemically-deficient disease states. Which brings us to:

(2) Drug companies propagate mainstream, scientific explanations of how antidepressants work that are part of a contemporary capitalist ideology

That was kind of a nerdy way to put it, BUT: Do patients/consumers feel relief because their antidepressant has worked on an underlying disease pathology, as the drug ads would have us believe?

poor little egg! there's a nice bird RIGHT NEXT TO YOU!

where'd the bird go?

BOO-YAH! THERE'S the fucking bird!

Or, do antidepressants actually induce psychoactive states, like sedation or stimulation or altered sense perception?

(from a 2003 MadTV parody using the Zoloft-style ads to promote Ecstasy)

This not a straightforward ‘objective,’ ‘scientific’ question. This is a question about the kind of language we choose to describe what a drug does. Correcting a “chemical imbalance” sounds squarely medical and socially appropriate. “Altered sense perception” sounds too much like how we are used to talking about illicit or illegal drugs, as if their psychopharmacology were a completely different animal than what Big Pharma peddles. Of course, it’s absolutely crucial that the pharmaceutical industry sounds like it is in the business of generating health and normality, not pleasure and dependency. For instance, one of the first direct-to-consumer pamphlets for Prozac claimed that, “Prozac doesn’t artificially alter your mood and it is not addictive. It can only make you feel more like yourself by treating the imbalance that causes depression.” What strange and preemptively defensive language … and what grandiose philosophical and epistemological claims about such a poorly-understood chemical!

Contrast how the National Institute of Drug Abuse (NIDA) describes MDMA (Ecstasy), whose pharmacology is quite similar to that of Prozac and Zoloft: “MDMA produces feelings of increased energy, euphoria, emotional warmth, and distortions in time, perception, and tactile experiences.” Can we imagine Pfizer making the same claims about Zoloft? And yet, this is what individuals sometimes actually report experiencing.

Part of what makes such psychopharmaceutical claims part of a capitalist ideology is their relationship to a distinctly Western-style of consumption in which we seek out and buy commodities to fashion our own unique personal identities. We buy things to become who we were always meant to be. (For critical theory buffs, start with Jean-Paul Baudrillard’s analysis of how, over the past few decades, capitalism has started to focus on the consumer — and not just the laborer — as a key site of exploitation.) Psychopharms are no different. Note the language of the above Prozac pamphlet: “It can only make you feel more like yourself …” Whereas users of illicit drugs like MDMA and LSD hail them as ways to go beyond oneself, or to explore oneself, the drug industry offers us psychopharmaceuticals as a return to our true selves. To the point, the tagline for Paxil advertisements used to be, “With the help of Paxil you can see someone you haven’t seen in awhile – yourself. Hey, I remember you.”

So, in this society, we consume antidepressants to fulfill our roles as outstanding consumer-citizens. But we consume marijuana or Ecstasy and become aberrant, unproductive drains on society. Which brings us to:

(3) We live in a hypocritical society that denies non-prescription self-medication while simultaneously encouraging a behemoth pharmatocracy

(First, this claim reminds us that the pharmaceutical industry does not exist in a vacuum. These companies are easy targets — and should most definitely be targeted — but we need to keep in mind that our contemporary experiences with drugs emerge from a complicated nexus of relationships between Big Pharma, government regulatory agencies, physicians, consumer groups, and beyond …)

On the one hand, the U.S. government denies individuals rights to grow, synthesize or consume psychotropic substances, whether it’s marijuana, opium, LSD, or methamphetamine. (This is a topic that I will give special attention to in later blogs.) On the other hand, psychotropic drug-taking has become a cornerstone of global capitalism, as corporate pharmaceutical paternalism takes over under the guise of “health” as a cultural imperative (so much so that the drugs are ending up in the water, remember?) The very facts — or, more properly, factoids — that the State-cum-pharmaceutical-industry propagates about mental health are circular: The notion that there is a high prevalence of depression in the United States is largely based on antidepressant prescription rates. So, the more people taking antidepressants = the more people counted as suffering from depression. “Depression” becomes reified as a bonafide epidemiological entity, and the pharmaceutical industry touts growing antidepressant rates as mere evidence that they are unearthing an “undertreated” (!) illness.

The capitalist, expansionist logic of this medical system is scary. Antidepressants do not work very well; their prevalence bloats the pharmaceutical companies’ and physicians’ profits; and their commercial success gets reinterpreted as a medical rationale for why we should consume more and more of them.

All this makes me feel like Nietzsche looked at the end of his life:


Download YouTube Video | YouTube to MP3 | Replay Media Catcher
So let’s start changing the rules of this game.

beginning

August 21, 2011

My blog begins. Words tomorrow. But, here, we are clearly off to an auspicious start:

 

Seo